How do we define Knowledge? This is a fundamental question that epistemologists debate and have formed numerous arguments towards. In Chapter 3, Pritchard suggest that the task to define knowledge is centered on the problem of criterion. The problem of criterion proposes two claims, the first being, “I can only identify instances of knowledge provided I already know what the criteria for knowledge are” (Pritchard 20). The second claim is “I can only know what the criteria for knowledge are provided I am already able to identify instances of knowledge” (Pritchard 21). As epistemologists, these claims give us two options. We can either assume we know the criteria for knowledge and use them to identify cases of knowledge (methodism), or we can assume that we can identify cases of knowledge and deduce the criteria for knowledge from similarities between these cases (particularism). These two methods counter each other and split epistemologists into separate beliefs about how to go about finding a definition for knowledge.
Although Pritchard stresses in Chapter 3 the importance of justification for one’s belief, he also states that matters are not that straightforward. This is due to the work of Edmund Gettier, who throws a wrench in the classical theory of knowledge. Pritchard presents us with an example where John reads the correct time from a stopped clock. In the case, John meets the conditions for the classical theory of knowledge; however, John’s JTB is based on luck. Gettier therefore argues that there is a fault in the JTB definition of knowledge due to the fact that luck can sometimes still sneak in. According to Gettier, John would not have knowledge.
Naturally, Gettier’s counter-examples to the classical theory of knowledge caused uproar in the philosophy/epistemology community. In response, epistemologists have attempted to narrow the gap between JTB and knowledge, “… a natural idea is to amend one’s analysis of knowledge by including an explicit ‘anti-luck’ condition” (Ichikawa). One major concern is the factor of presuppositions in Gettier’s work. Can we say that you have knowledge if one has a justified true belief and none of the presuppositions are false? Pritchard explains, “… it is difficult to spell out this idea of a presupposition such that it is strong enough to deal with Gettier cases and yet not so strong that it prevents us from having most of the knowledge what we think we have” (26). The complex question of what defines as a presupposition is raised. D. M. Armstrong argues that, “Gettier’s examples are defective because they rely on the false principle that false propositions can justify one’s belief in other propositions” (Feldman 68). Between these opposing beliefs, there is a middle ground where we must have an understanding of presuppositions so that Gettier cases hold, yet non-Gettier cases are not affected by this understanding.
So have we found a method yet that will help us arrive at a definition for knowledge? For every theory of how to begin defining knowledge that has been presented to us thus far, we have been given counter-examples. Pritchard presents us with methodism and particularism and Gettier finds problems with the JTB account of knowledge that Feldman then goes on to counter. Feldman writes, “If his evidence is true, or only if he knows it to be true, there are still counter-examples to the justified true belief analysis of knowledge of the Gettier sort” (69). As Pritchard concludes at the end of this chapter, we do not have a clear method that gives us a generally acknowledged unambiguous definition for knowledge. The question is, with so many opposing methods and counter-examples, will we ever?
Outside Source: Ichikawa, Jonathan Jenkins and Steup, Matthias, “The Analysis of Knowledge”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/knowledge-analysis/>.
What’s interesting is how we already “know” what knowledge is and are merely trying to find a definition that fits our preconceived notion of what knowledge is. How do we seem to innately know what knowledge is if we can’t even figure out a definition for it?
Donald I have a question for you. After reading Nozick (and probably in the future reading more arguments on what knowledge is) do you think we will ever be able to define knowledge in one succinct way?
Additionally, I think you were correct in identifying that we have to find a middle ground between “an understanding of presuppositions so that Gettier cases hold, yet non-Gettier cases are not affected by this understanding.” It could be possible that this middle ground might be an entirely new idea that does not relate to Gettier’s ideas or Feldman’s ideas.
That is a good question Natalie. I believe in the future, philosophers such as Feldman, Nozick and Gettier will continue to debate and critique the definition for knowledge. As I mentioned in my post, for every theory we have been presented with thus far, we have also been given counter examples. I see no reason to think that philosophers in the future will stop questioning each others methods in defining knowledge and coming up with further counter examples. Philosophers naturally ponder and probe at each other’s works and it is for this reason that I don’t believe we will every come to a truly widely accepted definition for Knowledge.
After this week’s reading and in class discussions, one of the biggest problems with an epistemological approach to defining knowledge I found was the problem of the criterion. As you stated in your initial posting, the problem consists of two claims that are based off of each other. This forces philosophers to assume at least one of the two claims, as you said, either the methodism or particularism approach. However, if one of the claims is always assumed, does that not also make the “true knowledge” assumed to an extent? This creates a fine line between epistemology and skepticism, which is the point that Nozick briefly alludes to in the last line of the first part of his essay. My question for you, or anyone else who reads this is: out of methodism, particularism, and skepticism, which approach logically upholds the best when searching for true belief?
As methodism and particularism are contrasting beliefs, Feldman proposes that as philosophers we must side with one or the other. Furthermore, concerning scepticism, Feldman writes, “One of the main advantages of methodism is that it doesn’t begin by assuming the falsity of scepticism, since it leaves it an open question whether there is anything that meets the criteria for knowledge” (22). In other words, do the criteria for knowledge or a justified true belief ever lead us to examples of knowledge? It is still in question whether out of methodism, particularism, and scepticism ther is one in particular that logically upholds the best when searching for true belief. As Feldman explains in Chapter 3, there is much more to knowledge than merely true belief.