
It is rare to hear the words “compassionate” and “homicide” in the same phrase. However, in the case of Tracy Latimer, a so-called “compassionate homicide” ended her young life. In 1994, Tracy’s father, Robert, murdered Tracy to relieve her from her life of suffering due to severe cerebral palsy. Three years later, he was issued a constitutional exemption from the typical penalty for second-degree murder, reducing his sentence from life in prison to a mere two years. This court ruling is controversial, leaving us with important questions about the implications of excusing Robert Latimer’s “mercy killing” of his 12-year old daughter (Thomas, 2014).
While Robert’s actions cannot be undone, this case begs us to ask: was it morally right to kill Tracy with the intention of freeing her from pain? In order to answer this question, we must understand the facts of the case. First, Latimer believed killing Tracy was the right thing to do, arguing that her quality of life was so poor that death itself was a better alternative. It is clear that Robert’s actions were in good faith. Described by the judge as a “loving and protective parent”, Robert had his daughter’s best interests at heart. Or, at least, what he thought were his daughter’s best interests.
As discussed in the case, there is a general consensus that he had good intentions; however, his intentions do not make this action morally right. In fact, killing Tracy was an extreme example of surrogate decision-making gone wrong. Because of Tracy’s disability, she was unable to express her wishes, giving the decision-making role to her parents. However, how is Robert positive that this is what Tracy would have wanted if she does not have the capability to express it?
This uncertainty is at the heart of why Robert’s actions were morally unjust. Just because Tracy lacks what most of us could not imagine living without (the ability to talk, walk, and feed herself) does not mean her value as a person is any less than someone without a disability. Furthermore, Robert can not be sure that her quality of life is diminished, either. How do we know she did not enjoy life in her own way? In fact, the very definition of “quality of life” as defined by the WHO is the “individual’s perception of their position in life”, not the perception of someone else (WHO, 1997). Therefore, it is not Robert’s place to decide when her life should be over, as he cannot possibly know for sure that this is what she wants.
Robert is not alone in this viewpoint. It is not uncommon for the able-bodied to perceive their own quality of life as higher than that of a disabled person. For example, a survey of emergency medical professionals found that only 17% believed their quality of life would be average after a severe spinal cord injury, compared to 86% of actual survivors (Senelick, 2013). In this case, we have to remember that these types of pessimistic attitudes are personal opinions and do not justify Robert’s actions.
The implications of Robert’s sentence in this case extend far beyond the life of his family. Advocates of those with disabilities worry this type of treatment will lead us down a slippery slope where treating people with disabilities as “less than” the able-bodied is justified. As Pat Danforth of the City Council of Canadians with Disabilities states, “We’re telling every senior citizen, every quadriplegic, anyone injured in a car accident that their life is of diminished value” (Thomas, 2014).
Some may argue that Tracy’s quality of life was indeed diminished by the extreme pain she experienced. There is debate on whether her pain was continuous or situational. However, Robert’s actions are still unwarranted for a few logistical reasons as well. First, this is not an act of assisted-suicide, but one of non-voluntary euthanasia. Choosing to kill Tracy in the back of his truck is an active decision, making him accountable for his actions. However, if Tracy were to be arrested during a surgical procedure and her parents opted to file a DNR order then this passive act of non-intervention would be better justified. It may seem like the two are similar; however, it is more a question of the immediate harms to Tracy herself. In this case, Tracy was not in any mortal danger the day her father killed her. Second, Robert did this act alone without consulting his wife or medical professionals about alternative options. As Arianna states in her blog post, he completely bypasses his wife’s say in this life-changing decision. If he were in this situation again, he could discuss his concerns and find a more humane and less rudimentary way to rid his child of her pain. However, it should not have been up to him.
In conclusion, Robert Latimer’s actions were morally wrong even though his intentions were in good faith as he violated the principle of autonomy and nonmaleficence. If other cases like this arise in the future, keep these words in mind: “There is great danger if we allow ourselves to view the disabled as people whose lives are not worth living” (Senelick, 2013).
REFERENCES
WHO. (1997). Measuring Quality of Life. WHOQOL, pp. 1. http://www.who.int/mental_health/media/68.pdf
Senelick, R. (2013). Reconciling Life and Quadriplegia. The Atlantic. https://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2013/12/reconciling-life-and-quadriplegia/281821/
CBC News. (2010). ‘Compassionate homicide’: The law and Robert Latimer. CBC News. http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/compassionate-homicide-the-law-and-robert-latimer-1.972561
Thomas, J. (2014). Well and Good. Broadview Press, 4th edition.