Case
Lucy Mait, a 45-year-old woman, found out she has the BRCA1 gene mutation, which meant she has a high risk of developing breast cancer. Lucy was having a very hard time processing this information and was referred to post-test genetic counseling to make sure she was fully informed of the implications of these results. Lucy has a 29 year old daughter, who is planning a wedding, and an 18 year old nice. Her doctor, Dr. Braesecke, has encouraged her to share the information with her daughter and nice so they can be tested as well but she is very reluctant to tell them. She claims that she needs more time to process the situation herself and that she does not want to ruin the mood of the upcoming positive events. All three of these women have been lifetime patients of Dr. Braesecke and he is put in a very tough position because he knows that early diagnosis and preventative measures can save lives.
Dilemma
Dr. Braesecke is faced with the dilemma between sharing the information with Lucy’s family, which breaks confidentiality, and respecting Lucy’s wishes by not saying anything.
Analysis
Dr. Braesecke is aware that “confidentiality can sometimes be ethically broke if there is a direct, imminent, and avoidable threat to the life of a third party” (CITE 259), but he is not sure whether this case fits this description. I argue that Dr. Braesecke ought to act under the principal of beneficence and inform the daughter and nice of this information. One can argue that this decision will violate the trust that is in the physician-patient relationship, which is important for future ongoing care. Dr. Braesecke can act under the utilitarian principle of justice, which states we ought to “seek to produce the maximal balance of positive value over disvalue – or the least possible disvalue, if only undesirable results can be achieved” (Beauchamp and Childress 254). In this case the benefit of telling two patients they are at high risk of having this mutation can possibly lead to preventative actions being taken that can save their lives. The disvalue in this case is violating the wishes of Lucy, who is just one patient. In this simple reasoning, two patients will be benefitted and only one would be offended. One can also look at the risks of keeping this information confidential compared to the risks of telling. The benefit of saving lives outweighs the harm of violating one’s autonomous decision. It can also be argued that Lucy will tell her family in the future, it is only a matter of timing. In response to that, it is impossible for Dr. Braesecke to be certain that Lucy will tell her family. The fact that Lucy may want to tell her family in the future but is not entirely sure speaks to the validity of the autonomy in her choice. Lucy has just been told she is at risk high risk for cancer, which other women in her family have had. According to Beauchamp and Childress, illness can limit one’s understanding of the situation and therefore limit one’s autonomy. Lucy’s judgment may be clouded and she may not fully understand the consequences of not telling her family, which can be seen in how she states she needs more time to process the situation. As their doctor, Dr. Braesecke is obligated by the principle of beneficence to prevent evil or harm (Beauchamp and Childress 152). He is in a situation where he has the ability to prevent serious harm by catching breast cancer in its early stages. One can argue that if Dr. Braesecke told Lucy’s family this act would be an act of hard paternalism. This hard paternalism is justified because, as stated above, the prevention of harm outweighs the risks of the action taken (Beauchamp and Childress 222). In this case Lucy’s genetic information ought not to be seen as entirely confidential because it may have direct implications on the well-being of others.
Sources
Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. New York: Oxford UP, 2009. Print.
Thomas, John E., Wilfrid J. Waluchow, and Elisabeth Gedge. “Case 9.3: Genetic Testing and Disclosure.” Well and Good: A Case Study Approach to Health Care Ethics. 4th ed. N.p.: n.p., n.d. 294-296. Print.